“Kids are Kids”: Benevolent Ignorance and the Omission of Race in Developmental Justice Reform
William Wannyn
SimpleOriginal

Summary

The legal focus on brain immaturity in juvenile justice ignores racial disparities. This "Benevolent ignorance" hides inconvenient data and overlooks the experiences of youth of color, perpetuating and obscuring racial bias.

2004

“Kids are Kids”: Benevolent Ignorance and the Omission of Race in Developmental Justice Reform

Keywords Ignorance; Juvenile justice; Brain immaturity; Neurolaw; Law and science; Child savers

Abstract

The criminal culpability of juvenile offenders remains a controversial and contested issue in the legal and public arenas in the United States. Since the mid-2000s, juvenile crime has been reframed by SCOTUS as a problem of brain immaturity. This article interrogates the omission of race from this new discourse of immaturity. First, I show that an alliance of learned societies, scholars, policy experts, legal professionals, and philanthropic foundations, which I call the new child savers, strategically sowed doubt about the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders to ensure the success of this new discourse of immaturity. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance to explain how they strategically concealed this inconvenient knowledge to achieve the socially valued goal of “saving children” from harsh sentences, and to escape public controversies over the racial overtones of risk assessment tools. Second, using Mills’ s concept of white ignorance, I argue that progressive elites and scholars involved in juvenile justice reform have historically ignored the lived experiences of juveniles of color. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of brain immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a colorblind explanation of juvenile crime that ignores the role of race in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Introduction

The question of how juvenile offenders should be treated by the law has been debated since the nineteenth century. At the heart of these debates is a “hybrid” (Lynch Michael, McNally and Jordan 2008, 43) controversy that neither law nor science has been able to resolve definitively: on what grounds should juvenile offenders be treated differently from adults? In the United States, the creation of the first juvenile court in 1899 and a semiautonomous field of juvenile justice in the following decades institutionalized the differential treatment of juvenile and adult offenders. In the last quarter of the twentieth century, however, the U.S. criminal justice system underwent a profound shift in its approach to juvenile delinquency. Beginning in the 1980s, the rehabilitative ideal and the sociomedical model that had guided the “treatment” of young offenders since the Progressive Era lost considerable ground to an actuarial and retributivist model of justice that emphasized punishment and incarceration over rehabilitation (Muncie 2008). This punitive turn drew on criminological evidence to implement an individual risk-based model in which young offenders were assessed, adjudicated, and sentenced according to the level of risk they posed to themselves and others.

Beginning in the mid-2000s, when most states had adopted tougher sentencing laws for juvenile offenders, the pendulum unexpectedly swung back from punishment to rehabilitation. In a series of three decisions1 the Supreme Court of the United States (SCOTUS) declared the death penalty and life without the possibility of parole (LWOP) for juvenile offenders unconstitutional under the Eighth Amendment of the U.S. Constitution.2 SCOTUS decisions were notable for going against the retributivist zeitgeist, even more so because the justices uncharacteristically supported their opinion with “new”3 scientific evidence from amicus curiae briefs4 claiming that juvenile crime is the byproduct of the immaturity of the adolescent brain.

In their amicus briefs, prestigious learned societies5 argued that adolescents, as a group, engage in risky behavior because their brains are immature, and should therefore be sentenced more leniently than adults. Their argument was based on emerging neuroscientific evidence about the “average” adolescent brain’s development—a scientific construct of the “normal” developmental trajectory of the human brain during adolescence. This discourse of immaturity portrays juvenile offenders as average immature adolescent risk-takers who will eventually mature out of delinquency. Its central claim is that because of their psychological and neurobiological immaturity, adolescents as a category should be treated more leniently than adults, and given a chance at rehabilitation.

The discourse of immaturity provided juvenile justice advocates with biological evidence to support decades of psychological and behavioral research on the psychosocial immaturity of adolescents. It succeeded in overturning the death penalty in 2005 where psychology alone had failed in Stanford v. Kentucky in 1989.6 As SCOTUS increasingly relied on the discourse of immaturity to buttress its opinion, legitimizing it further, it quickly gained popularity among juvenile justice advocates and in public discourse. Its influence eventually extended beyond juvenile justice, as lawyers, scholars, and advocates began to argue that young adult offenders under the age of 21 should be treated as leniently as juveniles, based on recent neuroscientific evidence that the brain continues to mature until at least the age of 25.7 The discourse of immaturity is now a core component of juvenile justice reform in the U.S. (National Research Council 2013), and it has reopened the debate in several states about the legal age threshold that separates juveniles from adults in criminal law.

Despite remarkable popularity, the discourse of immaturity has been criticized by scientists and legal scholars. Social scientists have accused neuroscientists of presenting findings as strong evidence of a causal link between neurobiological development and risky adolescent behavior (Sercombe 2010; Bessant 2008). They have also disputed that brain scan images are neurobiological evidence of adolescents’ inability to make rational decisions (Sercombe and Paus 2009; France 2012; Dumit 2014), emphasizing the technical complexity (Kelly 2012) and the epistemological apriorism that these images contain (Bessant and Watts 2012). Legal scholars have questioned SCOTUS’s overreliance on amicus briefs from learned societies in its decisions (Denno 2005), the legal applicability of the neurobiological immaturity argument (Maroney 2009), and the very admissibility of neuroscientific evidence of adolescent brain immaturity (Aronson 2007; 2009). Philosophers have questioned the relevance of neuroscience to the legal determination of criminal responsibility (Morse 2005), argued about the legal implications of treating juvenile offenders as distinct constitutional subjects (Berk 2019), and debated the policy ramifications of a neurodevelopmental framing of the role of adolescents in the polity (Yaffe 2018).

This article proposes a different kind of critique. It focuses not on what the discourse of immaturity is “made of” but rather on what it is “made without.” Despite important contributions, scholars have failed to interrogate the color-blindness of the discourse of immaturity. Racism has plagued the U.S. juvenile justice system since its inception, making nonwhiteness the leading risk factor for police brutality, arrest, and incarceration for young offenders (Alexander 2010; Cochran and Mears 2015; TenEyck et al. 2024). Yet the discourse of immaturity portrays all youth, regardless of color, as more at-risk than adults in their interactions with the criminal justice system because of their immature brains. Building on the work of STS scholars as well as sociologists and epistemologists of ignorance, I interrogate this omission of race by (1) demonstrating that racism had a structuring effect on the construction of the discourse of immaturity; and (2) by arguing this new scientific discourse perpetuates and reinforces the racial stratification processes of criminal justice.

I begin by showing how the discourse of immaturity was carefully crafted by some of the most prominent U.S. learned societies and a group of scholars, policy experts, and legal professionals under the tutelage of the MacArthur Foundation. Together, they sought to rehabilitate the child savers’ conception of juvenile offenders8 by updating it with the most recent neuroscientific findings on adolescent brain development. I show that in order to create this neurodevelopmental vision of juvenile delinquency, these new child savers had to disregard well-established but “uncomfortable knowledge” (Marris, Jefferson and Lentzos 2014) about “life-course persistent offenders” (Moffitt 1993), a small percentage of juvenile offenders who criminologists believe are responsible for a disproportionate amount of violent crime. I argue that the new child savers used this “strategic ignorance” (McGoey 2012) to distance themselves from the controversial, i.e., racist, public perception of this criminological knowledge about risk assessment. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance which I loosely define as the strategic concealment of inconvenient knowledge in order to achieve a socially valued goal, such as social justice. I argue that ignorance does not imply a counterproductive and malicious intent. Ignorance can be as productive as knowledge, and can be used to achieve progressive and noble goals, such as “saving children” from the death penalty

In the second part of this article, following recent calls to advance the study of race and racism in STS (Rodríguez-Muñiz 2016; Mascarenhas 2018; Hatch 2020), I interrogate the omission of race in developmental juvenile justice reform using Mills’s (2015, 217) concept of “white ignorance,” that is, “an ignorance among whites—an absence of belief, a false belief, a set of false beliefs, a pervasively deforming outlook—that [is] not contingent but causally linked to their whiteness.” I argue that benevolence, like malevolence, is tied to the positionality of ignorance producers and their worldview. In other words, while well-intentioned advocates may view the strategic use of ignorance as a necessary evil to achieve a goal they perceive as universally good, their assumptions about the inherent positive value of their cause may be constrained by the limited scope of their social position. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of immaturity further reinforces a “color-blind” explanation of crime and criminal justice in the United States that ignores the role of race and social class in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Ignorance and the Absent Presence of Race

Scholars have repeatedly warned about the dangers of biosocial models of crime (Rafter 2008), of using biotechnologies to monitor and profile citizens (Duster 2004), and of the reification of political categories (Duster 2005). Like behavioral genetics, the “neurocriminological vision” obscures the social and depoliticizes crime by ignoring how social factors interact with (neuro)biology (Fallin, Whooley and Barker 2019).

Yet the discourse of immaturity differs significantly from more traditional biosocial accounts of crime. First, earlier neuroscientific research on crime had focused on linking “specific biological abnormalities and the propensity to commit violent crime” (Rose 2007, 242), and on locating neurobiological markers of the “violent brain” (Rollins 2014), unlike the discourse of immaturity, which portrays juvenile delinquency as a normal process resulting from proximal (i.e., brain immaturity) and distal causes (i.e., evolution). Second, neurocriminology has traditionally sought to pinpoint the brain signatures associated with individual deviant behaviors, such as aggression or impulsivity, and of psychiatric disorders, such as psychopathy, in order to develop “screen-and-intervene” strategies designed to pre-emptively diagnose and neutralize “susceptible individuals” (Rose 2010). By contrast, the discourse of brain immaturity de-emphasizes individual risk in favor of a categorical approach that groups all youth under a psychobiological universal (“adolescents”) and all deviant and criminal behavior under an umbrella term, “risk-taking,” that encompasses a wide range of behaviors from cheating in school to premeditated murder. Third, and most importantly, while traditional biosocial research on crime tends to use essentialist conceptions of race uncritically (Larregue and Rollins 2019), the literature on brain development and delinquency never discusses the core issue of racial disparities in criminal justice. This omission is particularly intriguing given the legacy of racial segregation and mass incarceration in the United States.

STS scholars have argued that the “absent presence of race” (M’charek, Schramm and Skinner 2014) in science and technology expresses two sets of interrelated ideas. First, current racialized social inputs (categories, representations, beliefs, etc.) can be (in)advertently encoded in technoscientific artifacts as race-neutral and (re)produce/reinforce pre-existing racial stratification practices (e.g., Noble 2018; Benjamin 2020; Amrute 2020). In Europe, for example, the various constitutive elements of race appear under different guises, while others disappear and give rise to new presences, making race a slippery construct that “oscillates between reality and non-reality” (M’charek, Schramm and Skinner 2014, 462). So while race may not explicitly appear in DNA profiling technologies used to manage migrant populations, racially coded markers presented as raceneutral do participate in the process of racializing migrants (M’charek 2018).

Second, historical assumptions about racial hierarchies can remain “buried alive” (Duster 2003) in scientific paradigms while being perceived and mobilized in the public sphere as objective, race-neutral knowledge and technologies for social change. For example, rather than focusing on the “molecularization of race” (Duster 2005; Fullwiley 2007), Karkazis and Jordan-Young (2020) discuss how science is embedded in a racialized universe that it helps to reinforce. Using the metaphor of race as a “ghost variable,” they describe how historically accumulated racist assumptions about racial stratification are still embedded in contemporary science, technology, and medicine, leading to racist practices of categorization in and out of science.

These analyses tend to focus on the historical construction of a heterogeneous set of biological and social objects and dispositifs haunted by racialized practices and meanings. They shed light on how race is constantly reimagined, and how racism often remains embedded in social processes. However, they often neglect to explore how the social position, belief systems, and intentionality of those who (re)produce these processes of racial stratification shape their (un)conscious omission of race. As a result, it may appear that these absences passively and sometimes unintendedly reproduce racism. Ignorance, however, offers a broader range of interpretation of actors’ underlying motives. As feminist philosopher Marylin Frye (1983, 118) puts it: “Ignorance is not something simple: it is not a simple lack, absence or emptiness, and it is not a passive state.” Regarding contemporary biological research on crime, STS scholars have pointed out that the increasing elusiveness of race is linked to the political hypersensitivity of the relations between race and crime. This “taboo of race” (Rollins 2021) in the biological study of crime and violence has led many biosocial criminologists to avoid collecting, analyzing, and discussing race as a variable in their work (Duster 2006), and has made it more difficult for STS scholars to locate race and racism in scientific practices.

STS studies of scientific ignorance have provided insight into how omissions of knowledge can function as powerful political devices. On the one hand, scholars of ignorance have focused on the implicit role of epistemological ignorance in the formulation of research questions, data collection, and evidence-based implementation of new rules in regulatory science (Kleinman and Suryanarayanan 2013). The study of undone science (Frickel et al. 2010) shows how the intricacies of the systemic production of scientific ignorance are linked to neoliberalism. Undone science highlights the absence or insufficiency of research areas or topics that do not conform to the demands of a capitalist mode of governance (Hess 2020). As Hess (2016) argues, society plays a crucial role in pressuring institutions to conduct research in scientific civil areas that contradict the interests of dominant groups and/or helps marginalized groups make political demands.

On the other hand, agnotologists have emphasized the role of “strategic ignorance” (McGoey 2012) in the public sphere where opposing interest groups regularly mobilize scientific evidence according to their own political agendas. The political use of science can lead to the silencing of certain inconvenient scientific facts, as shown by Proctor (1994) in his study of the tobacco industry’s efforts to sow doubt about the carcinogenic effects of smoking, or to emphasize the uncertainty of science as shown by Oreskes and Conway (2011) in their work on conservative think tanks promoting distrust in climate change. As Proctor and Schiebinger (2008, 8) argue, commercially driven science can be used to “actively organiz(e) doubt, uncertainty or misinformation to help maintain ignorance.” Strategic ignorance also includes governmental or industrial practices of “sequestering” knowledge (Heimer 2012) by deliberately hiding inconvenient information behind opaque bureaucratic procedures, or by compartmentalizing access to information to isolated individuals or groups.

Thus, agnotology provides a powerful framework for identifying the intentional motivations of actors’ attempts to subvert laws, procedures, public scrutiny, or political oversight. However, case studies of ignorance tend to pit passive and intentional ignorance against each other (Fernández Pinto 2015, 295) as if they were mutually exclusive. On the one hand, agnotologists depict institutional practices of omission that passively favor the production of certain kinds of knowledge aligned with the dominant political ideology, at the expense of other subversive forms of knowledge. On the other hand, they portray ignorance as an active ploy used by government agencies and the private sector to hide embarrassing evidence. Moreover, agnotologists have primarily emphasized the “antiscientific,” counterproductive, and commercially driven nature of ignorance (Gross and McGoey 2015, 3). The production of ignorance is associated with “deviant science,” self-interest and deception (Frickel and Edwards 2014, 217). Furthermore, agnotologists seem to share the ethical premise that “bad” ignorance encapsulates all illegitimate uses of science to cause social prejudice, while “good” science can be viewed as any legitimate scientific knowledge designed and used for the common good. This implicit normative stance is reflected in the field’s focus on “morally reprehensible” uses of science, such as sowing doubt about climate change, denying the carcinogenic effects of tobacco, or making financial profit.

In this paper, I show that ignorance can be both passive and intentional. To be sure, the emphasis on strategic and fraudulent uses of ignorance by the “merchants of doubt” (Oreskes and Conway 2011) fails to capture the full range of omission practices and limits our understanding of action to conscious and purposeful intent. It relies on a thin conception of strategies because intentional strategies account for only a fraction of the actions of social actors. In fact, most strategies are neither intentional—since they do not follow objectively oriented lines—nor utilitarian since they are unconscious. Moreover, I suggest that the dichotomy between passive and strategic ignorance fails to account for the fact that strategies reflect both conscious and unconscious motives that are tied to agents’ positionality in the social world and relative to competing strategies. As feminist scholars and epistemologists of ignorance have argued, knowers are always positioned somewhere in the social space, “at once limited and enabled by the specificities of their locations” (Code 1993, 39). Group identity, experience, and social location shape assumptions and beliefs about the world and thus the upstream epistemological operations that appear plausible and coherent (Alcoff 2007, 48). As I argue in the second part of this article, understanding the full extent of the benevolent ignorance of race in the discourse of immaturity requires considering the “coloniality of knowledge” (Santos 2018, 8): not only what kinds of knowledge are silenced, omitted, and absent, but also who is speaking, from where, and in whose name.

Data and Methods

The data presented in this article are part of a larger research project on the origins and development of neurolaw in the United States. The analyses in this article are based on 37 in-depth semi-structured interviews conducted in the United States between September 2018 and May 2020 with U.S. academics, federal and state judges, government officials, juvenile justice advocates, crime victims’ organizations, and philanthropic foundations. Using a snowball sampling technique, participants were recruited based on their contributions to the field. They were asked questions about their involvement with the MacArthur Foundation, their role in producing and disseminating work at the intersection of law and neuroscience, and about their perspective on the benefits, pitfalls, and risks of using neuroscience to inform/reform the law. All interviews were transcribed verbatim and were analyzed using QDA Miner software. Given the prominence of the participants, I decided to keep their contributions anonymous and disclose only information directly relevant to this research.

In addition, I used the SCOTUS online library, the Heinonline database, and SCOTUS online multimedia archival websites, such as Scotusblog.com, Oyez.org and Supreme.justicia.com, to compile and analyze the legal materials of three landmark SCOTUS decisions: Roper v. Simmons (2005), Graham v. Florida (2010), and Miller v. Alabama (2012). These cases were chosen because they bucked the punitive trends of the 1990s, ending the death penalty and limiting the use of LWOP for juvenile offenders. The idea that minors are less mature than adults and should therefore be punished differently was by no means new. However, as I will show, the neurobiological framing of immaturity was created as a response to the weakening of the boundary separating juvenile and adult offenders in the penal system, and as a way to institutionalize a scientifically based legal precedent. The dataset constructed to assess the co-construction of the discourse of immaturity comprises publicly available material, including the three SCOTUS decisions, the briefs of all defendants and respondents, all the amicus briefs submitted to SCOTUS, and the audio recordings of each oral argument. Finally, I examined how the scientific literature cited in the amicus briefs of the American Medical Association (AMA) and the American Psychological Association (APA) was used to construct the discourse of immaturity.

I used a comparative discourse analysis (Gilbert and Mulkay 1984) to identify discursive (ir)regularities between the respondents’ discourse, the scientific literature, and the legal material. Amicus briefs from learned societies were particularly useful because of their hybrid nature as science-based legal artifacts, combining elements of scientific discourse with other discursive repertoires belonging to other “cultures of belief” encountered in court (Jasanoff 1998, 731–2), such as common sense and jurisprudence. Comparing scientists’ different repertoires allowed me to ask interviewees about the discrepancies between their scientific claims and their legal arguments (e.g., some participants’ involvement in risk assessment science and their progressive stance). STS has a long tradition of challenging scientific expertise in court (Collins and Evans 2002; Lynch and Cole 2005). But with few exceptions (Edmond 2002; Edmond and Mercer 2004; Edmond and Mercer 2006), scholars rarely include amicus briefs as a source of data. Amicus briefs are a privileged means for various third parties, scholars and non-scholars, to mobilize science in the legal arena, and to lobby judicial institutions. Their hybrid nature generates debate and disagreement among scientists because their scientific claims are perceived as tainted by advocacy (e.g., Elliott 1991; Barrett and Morris 1993). As such, they provide important insights into the “boundary work” (Gieryn 1983) at the intersection of science and law.

The Punitive Turn and the Superpredator Narrative

To understand how juvenile delinquency became a brain condition, we must first consider how young offenders were portrayed by criminologists, politicians, and the media in the 1980s and 1990s. In the 1970s and 1980s, U.S. criminologists claimed to have identified a subgroup of “high-risk delinquents” whose “propensity” to commit crimes began in childhood and continued into adulthood. Several U.S.-based longitudinal studies seemed to show that a small percentage of juvenile offenders (about 6 percent) committed nearly half of all crimes (Wolfgang, Figlio and Sellin 1972; Wolfgang 1983; Farrington, Ohlin and Wilson 1986). These juveniles were labeled “life-course persistent offenders” after the influential work of clinical psychologist Terrie Moffitt (1993), as opposed to “adolescence-limited offenders,” who represent the majority of juvenile delinquents that commit mostly minor crimes during adolescence and become law-abiding citizens as they enter adulthood.

Criminologists’ work on “high-risk delinquents” had a significant impact on the U.S. criminal justice system because it promised to uncover tangible risk factors and develop actuarial risk assessment tools that judges, probation officers and social workers could use to “separate the wheat from the chaff.” In the long run, it was expected to provide an actuarial framework for reducing the prison population and its associated costs, locking up only the “high-risk” 6 percent of offenders (Harcourt 2015, 238). This riskbased classification of offenders opened up the way for implementing a selective incapacitation approach, and was key to the reconfiguration of the juvenile justice field during what the CDC called the “epidemic of violence” of the 1990s.

The emphasis on “dangerous” youth and violent crime was also central to the public rearticulation of the “problem” of juvenile crime. The rise in juvenile arrest rates between the 1970s and 1990s was often used in political discourse to justify harsher criminal sanctions against minors. Although in the late 1990s juvenile arrests for violent offenses nationwide was the lowest in a decade (Snyder 1999), intense news coverage amplified the scale and public perception of the phenomenon (Muschert 2007, 351). In the mid-1990s, as the Democratic Party underwent an ideological shift to break with the public perception that Democrats were weak on crime, then-Congressman Joe Biden and presidential candidate Bill Clinton crafted the Violent Crime Control and Law Enforcement Act of 1994. Along with elected officials, the media reinforced public perceptions of dangerous and out-of-control youth, including disproportionate coverage of violent youth crime (Bazelon 2000, 165–7).

The Democrats’ actions provoked strong disapproval among progressive elites, who felt that their loyalties had been betrayed for political gain. A MacArthur Foundation administrator I interviewed recalls that the general feeling among liberals was that elected officials had lost sight of the founding principle of juvenile justice, that “kids are kids.” This sentiment would soon lead to an alliance of scholars, foundations, and learned societies to “rehabilitate rehabilitation.” In just a few years, these new child savers would strategically use science to reframe juvenile delinquency as a consequence of psychological and neurobiological immaturity, a “new” narrative that would prove highly effective in the legal arena.

The new Child Savers and the Discourse of Immaturity

In the mid-1990s, the MacArthur Foundation9 established the Research Network on Adolescent Development and Juvenile Justice (RNADJJ). Its primary goal was to counter the effects of the punitive turn by compiling scientific evidence showing that adolescents, as a group, are less culpable for their crimes than adults. The research group was deliberately structured differently from other traditional MacArthur research networks. A key member of the group explained to me that the Foundation’s intent was “to force us to develop research projects that had clear practical implications” and “to develop and disseminate scientifically sound information that would inform policy and practice.” Thus, the RNADJJ included not only academics and legal scholars, but also a judge, a prosecutor, a defense attorney and a juvenile justice advocate.

By the early 2000s, the RNADJJ had managed to gather enough psychological, behavioral, and neurodevelopmental data to articulate a new scientific explanation of juvenile delinquency that centered on the psychological and neurobiological immaturity of adolescents. In the courtroom, the contest for credibility is not so much about establishing the truth as it is about ending the case, so plausibility often wins out (Shapin 1995; Jasanoff 1998). Although evidence of causality between brain immaturity and delinquency remained elusive, the discourse of immaturity was plausible enough to have a major impact on juvenile sentencing laws. Beginning in 2004, the RNADJJ collaborated with prestigious learned societies to place the discourse of immaturity at the center of their amicus briefs in what became three landmark SCOTUS decisions. Building on their success in Roper (2005), Graham (2010), and Miller (2012), the new child savers continued to gather and disseminate scientific evidence about the psychobiological immaturity of young offenders at conferences, in workshops, and in state courts. The success of the discourse of immaturity is truly remarkable given the retributive zeitgeist of the period. But in order to successfully promote the idea that every juvenile should be “saved,” the new child savers had to ignore an inconvenient fact: the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders.

The Benevolent Ignorance of Inconvenient Knowledge

A central figure in the RNADJJ explained to me that from the outset researchers were asked to stay away from criminological explanations of juvenile delinquency, and to focus on psychology’s findings about “normal” adolescent development. In addition, the Foundation appointed as director a developmental psychologist with no prior experience in juvenile justice research. Criminology has traditionally othered juvenile offenders as deviant youth, and risk assessment classifications support the argument that some youths are beyond rehabilitation. By privileging a developmental approach, the Foundation posited that all juvenile offenders are average adolescents, and hoped to gather scientific data to support the argument that they are inherently different from adults.

The members of the RNADJJ were familiar with the work of criminologists on “high-risk” youth. In some of their earlier publications, they repeatedly discussed Moffitt’s (1993) developmental taxonomy, which distinguishes “life-course persistent offenders” from “adolescent-limited offenders” (e.g., Steinberg and Cauffman 1999; Steinberg and Scott 2003). They also recognized that these two categories of juvenile offenders have different “risk factors:”

the overall pattern of findings suggests some possible differences between the correlates of serious offending (which are neuropsychological, autonomic10 and self-control) versus minor delinquency (which are self-control, but not neuropsychological or autonomic). (Cauffman, Steinberg and Piquero 2005, 160–1)

While initially acknowledging the work of criminologists, over time the new child savers distanced themselves from the idea that juvenile offenders could be divided into “high-risk” and “low-risk” groups. Rather than engaging this literature to formulate an evidence-based critique of its findings, they increasingly rejected its relevance to debates about the age of criminal responsibility. One way of doing this was to present a truncated interpretation of findings, for example by stating that “high-risk” offenders represent only a small fraction of all offenders, while failing to mention their overrepresentation in the prison population and their involvement in 50 percent of all crimes. Another way was to ignore the distinction between “high” and “low” risk offenders altogether, lumping all juvenile offenders together under umbrella terms like “adolescents” or “kids,” and portraying them as “‘moving targets’ for assessment of character and future dangerousness” (Brief for APA in Roper v. Simmons 2005, 3).

Making predictions about future delinquency based on adolescents’ risky behavior was reframed as an “uncertain business” (Steinberg and Scott 2003, 1014). For example, a significant portion of the APA’s amicus brief in Roper argued that science and medicine cannot reliably assess whether juvenile offenders will continue to commit crimes into adulthood, and that psychopathy, which is commonly associated with “high-risk” offenders, is not a reliable diagnosis for adolescents. Summarizing its main arguments, the APA wrote:

The absence of proof that assessments of adolescent behavior will remain stable into adulthood invites unreliable capital sentencing based on faulty appraisals of character and future conduct. (Brief for APA in Roper v. Simmons 2005, 24)

Five years later in Graham, the same arguments were mentioned only in footnotes (Brief for APA in Graham v. Florida 2010, 22, footnote 44). They would reappear briefly in the APA’s brief in Miller, but only to conclude that:

there is no reliable way to determine that a juvenile’s offenses are the result of an irredeemably corrupt character; and there is thus no reliable way to conclude that a juvenile—even one convicted of an extremely serious offense —should be sentenced to life in prison, without any opportunity to demonstrate change or reform. (Brief for APA in Miller v. Alabama 2012, 25)

By sowing doubt about the reliability of risk-assessment science, the new child savers reframed the debate about the dangerousness of “high-risk” offenders into a discussion of the more benign figure of the “immature” and brash adolescent. Risk remained an integral part of the discourse on juvenile delinquency, not as an expression of an irredeemable flaw in some “at-risk” adolescents, but as a manifestation of the normal process of growing up. From there on, adolescents were portrayed as “risk takers to a far greater degree than adults” (Brief for APA in Roper v. Simmons 2005, 6). A neuroscientist I interviewed who worked with the MacArthur Foundation on various juvenile justice projects at the time explained the Foundation’s strategy:

The philosophy really (was) that no juvenile should ever be incarcerated.… The MacArthur Foundation was particularly interested in not funding studies that would ever show that someone’s brain was high-risk. They wanted to show that every juvenile brain was amenable to treatment.

To be sure, the primary goal of the new child savers was benevolent, and ignoring scientific evidence that directly contradicted the seemingly more inclusive discourse of immaturity was essential to its success. However, this benevolent ignorance of risk assessment science is surprising for several reasons. Beginning in the 1980s, risk assessment strategies and tools played a critical role in the implementation of a “new penology” (Feeley and Simon 1992) in the criminal justice system, as authorities focused their attention on monitoring, profiling, and neutralizing “high-risk” youth (Hannah-Moffat 2013). By the early 2000s, risk classifications of juvenile offenders had become consensual among criminologists and widespread in the justice system. Additionally, emerging neurocriminological research claimed to have identified structural and functional neurobiological markers of antisocial behavior and aggression in “high-risk” youths (Ortiz and Raine 2004; Sterzer et al. 2007; Huebner et al. 2008; Passamonti et al. 2010).

Most importantly, the MacArthur Foundation had been involved in promoting risk-assessment tools in the criminal justice system for more than a decade. As one interviewee explained:

The MacArthur Foundation has funded the development of the psychopathy checklist…in the MacArthur Violence Risk Assessment Study. They published and funded…work on psychopathy and children and adolescents… they funded the development of risk assessment variables for kids. They have a history of doing this risk assessment work.

Like many other organizations, the MacArthur Foundation supported the actuarial turn in the criminal justice system and the shift from danger to risk. Throughout the 1990s and 2000s, the Foundation participated in several efforts to develop and implement risk-assessment tools, on the basis that identifying and classifying young offenders would further the rehabilitative goal of the justice system. In 1990, for example, the Foundation initiated the Project on Human Development in Chicago Neighborhoods to assess the risk factors that contribute to “the pathways to juvenile delinquency, adult crime, substance abuse, and violence” (Inter-University Consortium for Political and Social Research 2024). As the discourse of immaturity spread in the mid-2000s, the Foundation continued to invest in developing and refining these tools through its Models for Change initiative, a program to disseminate “best practices” in juvenile justice. A key figure in this initiative explained in an interview:

My primary involvement with the MacArthur Foundation was the Models for change initiative. We had a research network for that. We were in the field working with juvenile justice agencies in 16 states, informing them about adolescent development, the brain and how this affects risk for reoffending, creating an assessment measure to asses risk of reoffending.

How do we explain this paradox? Why did the new child savers ignore risk assessment science while supporting its implementation in the juvenile justice system? Although risk assessment practices were becoming more widespread, the fact that some juveniles could be labeled “high risk” and beyond rehabilitation ran counter to the rehabilitative ideal underlying the discourse of immaturity. Above all, the new child savers’ benevolent ignorance of risk-assessment science aimed to escape controversies surrounding the latent racism of some of its political uses.

The Superpredator: Science, Racism and Politics

The rise in crime rates in the last quarter of the twentieth century is often portrayed as the cause of the transformation of the United States into a “penal state” (Wacquant 2009). Many social scientists have argued that racial attitudes, not crime rates, were the driving factor behind white Americans’ support of tougher laws and anti-welfare measures (Alexander 2010, 68). White voters were concerned about the demographic transformation of U.S. society and the rapid increase in the proportion of racial minority youth (Males and Brown 2014, 6). The “baby boom” of the 1960s had led to a rapid increase in the relative proportion of young people of color from 15 percent of the youth population in the 1960s, to over 40 percent in the early 2000s (Males 2009, 6).

This demographic shift particularly preoccupied scholars on the conservative fringe of U.S. political science and criminology, such as James Q. Wilson, Charles Murray, James Fox, and John Dilulio. In the mid-1990s, these scholars fueled popular concerns about violence and crime by heralding the emergence of a new “species” of juvenile delinquent, which they portrayed as a harbinger of the collapse of American society. “Superpredators” were described as:

radically impulsive, brutally remorseless youngsters…who murder, assault, rape, rob, burglarize, deal deadly drugs, join gun-toting gangs, and create serious communal disorders. (Bennett and Dilulio 1996, 27)

Then-Princeton University political science and public policy professor John Dilulio and like-minded colleagues claimed that young black men were committing violent crimes at twice the rate of their white counterparts. They predicted that this trend, combined with the rapid demographic growth of black youth, would lead to a wave of “super crime-prone young males” over the next decade (Dilulio 1995). The superpredator theory rested on three basic premises. First, the changing demographics of the U.S. population would lead to a collapse of American, i.e., White, Anglo-Saxon, Protestant moral values. Second, children growing up without “loving, capable and responsible” parents in “abusive, violence-ridden, fatherless, Godless, and jobless” neighborhoods would inevitably become remorseless violent criminals (ibid.). Third and most importantly, it relied on a key criminological finding to support its claims: that a minority of “high-risk” offenders commit a disproportionate percentage of violent crimes.

The superpredator theory had considerable political resonance. In their efforts to maintain public support for tougher laws against young people, Democrats drew on this stereotype of violent and uncontrollable youths ready to destroy American society. The superpredator trope became an integral part of the Democrats’ populist rhetoric during Clinton’s first term. Unlike Dilulio and his colleagues, the Democrats never explicitly equated superpredators with young black men in the inner cities—but the underlying racial coding was not lost on anyone. Moreover, the deployment of state surveillance in the social space left little doubt as to who the “enemy” was. As Wacquant (2009, 67, italics in the original) wrote: “Class and ethnic selectiveness was achieved primarily by the targeting of certain geographic zones, which guaranteed that the categories composing their residents would be the primary if not exclusive ‘beneficiaries’ of the newfound policing zeal and penal largesse of the state.” Groups targeted by this return to “traditional” values and conservative moral discipline were the poor, the immigrants, the drug users, and especially young black men.

In the 1990s, risk assessment tools became the gold standard for assessing juvenile offenders, but also for attempting to predict “dangerousness” outside the prison walls. Central to this “new modality of surveillance” (Castel 1983, 123) was the systematic screening of so-called “at-risk” populations. In the early 1990s the MacArthur Foundation partnered with the National Institute of Justice, the National Institute of Mental Health, and the U.S. Department of Education to launch a crime prevention campaign called the Program on Human Development and Criminal Behavior. Based at the Harvard School of Public Health, the program screened children in Chicago to identify biological, psychological, and social factors that predispose them to crime (Rose 2007, 245). Scientists would follow cohorts of children over eight years to identify biomarkers that predict crime. As part of the broader framework of the National Violence Initiative (NVI) launched by the National Institute of Mental Health in the early 1990s, the program shared its ambitions for early identification of dangerous youth to nip potential “superpredators” in the bud.

These programs generated a great deal of opposition in the scientific field and in the public sphere. Reactions to the NVI were particularly strong because it targeted inner-city black youth with a screening campaign designed to identify children biologically predisposed to violence. The use of risk assessment strategies to prevent juvenile delinquency and predict recidivism came under fire when critics began to argue that risk was a “proxy for race” (Harcourt 2015). The racist connotations of some of the work underlying the program and its political recuperation to reinforce strategies for controlling the underprivileged racial minorities, cast a negative light on the research on “high-risk” youth. The straw that broke the camel’s back came in 1992 when Frederick K. Goodwin, then director of the Alcohol, Drug Abuse, and Mental Health Administration and a key player in the NVI, compared black inner-city youths to “monkeys in the jungle” during a public meeting of a departmental mental health advisory committee. The ensuing controversy reinforced the public perception of the underlying racist nature of the initiative and led to demonstrations against the NVI. As a result of complaints from the Congressional Black Caucus, the NAACP, and mounting public pressure, the NIH withdrew its financial support for the Maryland Conference on Genetics and Crime scheduled for September 1992 at the University of Maryland, and canceled the MacArthur-funded Program on Human Development and Criminal Behavior.

Philanthropic foundations are reputational organizations, and their success in attracting support depends on their ability to maintain a public image that aligns with the political inclinations of their benefactors (Bourdieu 2011, 133). With this in mind, the MacArthur Foundation was careful to separate its work on juvenile justice reform at the policy level from the controversial issue of risk assessment in the justice system, and its racial overtones. In the years that followed, however, the Foundation renewed funding for risk assessment research, an approach that remained central to juvenile justice. But as the discourse of immaturity gained traction in the legal arena, the new child savers continued to ignore risk assessment scholarship while producing and disseminating further evidence of the role of brain immaturity in juvenile delinquency.

The Dark side of Benevolence

The benevolent ignorance of risk assessment science has allowed the new child savers to erode the grip of retributivism on juvenile offenders. Nevertheless, it reflects a commitment to “doing good,” as well as a worldview that is inherently tied to the positionality of its proponents. In this section, I consider how “white ignorance” (Mills 2007) has historically blinded the child savers to racial inequities, and how the discourse of brain immaturity reproduces a racially ignorant explanation of juvenile delinquency, oblivious to the social realities of the legal encounters of youths of color with the juvenile justice system.

The White Ignorance of the Child Savers

The new child savers’ commitment to juvenile justice reform is a continuation of the work of the Child Study Movement. At the turn of the twentieth century, this “reformist nebula” (Topalov 1999) advocated for legal reforms to make education compulsory, abolish child labor, and create special legal procedures for juvenile offenders (Bakan 1971, 981). The child savers’ successful campaign to create juvenile courts in 1899 was based on the scientific work of Stanley Hall, the father of developmental psychology and a key member of the child study movement. Hall believed that adolescence was the pivotal stage in individual development, and that it should be prolonged as much as possible to bring out “psychological progress” (Arnett 2006, 191). Like Hall, progressive elites believed that premature entry into adulthood corrupted childhood innocence, and placed a brake on the progress of American society. Social scientists have criticized the “moral enterprise” (Becker 1966, 145) of the child savers arguing that their charitable intentions concealed a “program of moral absolutism” (Platt 1969, 27) designed to extend state control over the previously unregulated “deviant” behavior of disenfranchised and marginalized populations (Garland 2001, 27). For example, the precocious entry into adulthood of working-class children, who often worked in factories or as street vendors (Takanishi 1978, 13) and were invested with adult responsibilities, was framed as contrary to Hall’s conception of “normal” development, and justified the “rehabilitation” of poor children in reformatories (Muncie and Goldson 2012, 342).

The child savers’ emphasis on age at the expense of race and social class was tied to their positionality in American society. Because of their privileged position, their worldview was blinded by what Mills calls “white ignorance”—where ignorance is the necessary manifestation of a political system of “global white supremacy” governed by a “racial contract” whereby people in privileged positions adhere to an “inverted epistemology,” i.e., a specific pattern of psychologically and socially functional cognitive dysfunctions, that renders the underprivileged worldview unintelligible to them (Mills 1997, 18). Central figures of the child study movement such as Jane Addams, Lucy Flower, and Julia Lathrop were white, wealthy, women philanthropists who upheld Jim Crow segregation (Goodman, Page and Phelps 2017, 53). Thus, the benevolence of child savers toward children was not evenly distributed, and was primarily directed toward white children. Moreover, the juvenile courts they helped create differentiated, discriminated against, and rejected black youth. From their inception, they produced a “two-tiered” system of justice that ordered lenient treatment for children of the ruling class, and the institutionalization of alien and disadvantaged youth (Soung 2011, 434–5). In the southern states, the scarcity of juvenile courts further reinforced racial segregation by restricting access to white youth and condemning black youth to the more punitive treatment of adult prisons (Ward 2012, 98).

The Color-Blindness of the Brain Immaturity Plea

The original and the new child savers share a “soteriological ambition” (Stoczkowski 2019, 31) to “save children” from the corrupt world of adults by gathering and using developmental knowledge about young people to demand legislative reform. While the new child savers do not endorse racism, their discourse of immaturity is racially ignorant in two ways.

First, historically, the developmental norms of childhood have been constructed from measurements of white privileged children11 and used for public and health policy purposes, as well as to “educate” poor and racialized parents about “best” parenting practices. Psychologists’ claims about “normality” have been based primarily on white, privileged male students, whom researchers perceive as “the best representatives of normality by virtue of their race, class, and gender” (Prescott 2002, 20). As I have shown elsewhere (Wannyn 2022), the discourse of immaturity also relies on studies conducted among white upper-middle-class, educated, and healthy youth in the United States.12 Because they are limited in what they can accomplish experimentally by the material at hand and by the need to achieve “doable problems” (Clarke and Fujimura 1992, 9), neuroscientists continue to rely on convenience sampling. Thus, until recently participants in studies of adolescent brain development have been predominantly drawn from the white, privileged population that is most accessible to neuroscientists.13 The lack of racial and socioeconomic diversity in brain research mirrors similar problems in other fields of research, where scientists have relied overwhelmingly on white participants to characterize “normal” lungs (Braun 2014), hearts (Pollock 2012), bone density (Fausto-Sterling 2008), or hair and hormones (Carlin and Kramer 2020). The “default whiteness” (Benjamin 2020, 170) of the “average” adolescent brain raises fundamental questions about the generalizability of these findings to the U.S. adolescent population, and about the inferences that can be made about young offenders, a population that is disproportionately nonwhite and underprivileged, and whose developmental trajectories differ significantly from that of their white privileged counterparts. Here, “unmarked whiteness” (Frankenberg 2001) produces a false universalism in which the “white brain” dictates the “constitutive norm” (Mills 2007, 25) of adolescent brain development while obscuring its ontologically racialized nature.14

Second, despite its undeniable symbolic value, the discourse of immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a color-blind vision of juvenile justice fraught with problematic assumptions about youth, crime and race. The neurocentric explanation of delinquency runs counter to structural explanations of what Alexander (2010) calls the “new caste system,” i.e., the mass incarceration of record numbers of young black men since the 1970s. The emphasis on rehabilitating rehabilitation does not take into account the deeply racialized history of juvenile courts in the United States, nor does it equate social progress with racial justice. It fails to recognize that the majority of juvenile offenders are involved with the justice system not because of brain immaturity, but because of their race. Moreover, the omission of race obscures the fact that in the U.S. justice system the “presumption of immaturity” too often remains the privilege of white youth, while black youth are disproportionately treated as adults (Nunn 2001). Justice actors tend to perceive black youth as more “adult,” violent and aggressive than white adolescents (Graham and Lowery 2004). They are perceived as less “childlike” and more responsible than their white counterparts (Goff et al. 2014). As Henning (2012, 420) wrote: “decision makers, such as police, probation officers, and prosecutors, treat youth of color more harshly than white youth in part because of an implicit bias to ignore developmental immaturity in youth of color.” As a result, the immaturity defense may ultimately have little effect on reducing racial discrimination against young people of color, given that juvenile transfer laws to adult criminal courts remain widespread and have historically been used disproportionately against youth of color to undermine their right to differential treatment (Buss 2022, 886).

Conclusion

Benevolent ignorance poses a moral dilemma for social scientists and STS scholars. On the one hand, the new child savers were able to institutionalize a “new” discourse on juvenile delinquency that halted the punitive turn in the United States. This accomplishment should not be understated because the pendulum continues to swing between rehabilitation and punishment. As evidenced by the recent SCOTUS decision in Jones v. Mississippi (2020), many states and courts still believe that “children who kill” should be tried as adults. On the other hand, the “writing of crime into race” (Muhammad 2010) remains absent from the discourse of immaturity. Its reductionist and color-blind explanation of juvenile delinquency ignores how racial inequalities shape young people’s criminal trajectories, fails to capture the deeply racialized nature of the justice system, and obscures the fact that social stratification is both the underlying cause and a direct consequence of incarceration (Wakefield and Uggen 2010). While white and non-white youth may share a propensity for risktaking and impulsive behavior, the punitive consequences of such behavior are disproportionately borne by poor young black men (Henning 2012, 411). Therefore, while the legal and political influence of the discourse of immaturity has resulted in important reform, it has also legitimized a neurobiological understanding of juvenile crime that mirrors the progressive elites’ racialized view of young offenders at the expense of the lived experience of racial minorities.

Science has been instrumental in reshaping juvenile justice in the United States in recent decades. Similar debates in Europe have relied not on science, but on sociopolitical and moral frameworks that emphasize the role of the polity in protecting minors, rather than on adolescents’ immaturity15 (Muncie and Goldson 2006; Sallée 2016). In the United States, legal actors and juvenile justice advocates have turned to neuroscience because they believe that it can objectively, and neutrally, demonstrate that minors are fundamentally different from adults. But scientific knowledge and technologies are co-produced (Jasanoff 2004) with existing social structures, institutions, and ideologies. The credibility and legitimacy of biologization depend on social frameworks in which legitimate institutions or social groups recognize it as such.

Neuroscientists’ ability to link their data to pre-existing conceptions of juvenile delinquency is key to their legitimacy in the criminal justice field. Thus, neurocriminology has maintained its authority in the justice system because it echoes the longstanding belief among probation officers and prison personnel that serious juvenile offenders are fundamentally different from others. Likewise, the discourse of immaturity renews the legal tradition of viewing minors as a population inherently less culpable than adults. Therefore, the competition between neuroscientific explanations of crime, i.e., crime as a brain abnormality, as brain immaturity, or as brain trauma, can only be resolved temporarily through the “categorical alignment” (Epstein 2008, 92) of official and scientific classifications, rather than through the establishment of a definitive scientific truth.

Abstract

The criminal culpability of juvenile offenders remains a controversial and contested issue in the legal and public arenas in the United States. Since the mid-2000s, juvenile crime has been reframed by SCOTUS as a problem of brain immaturity. This article interrogates the omission of race from this new discourse of immaturity. First, I show that an alliance of learned societies, scholars, policy experts, legal professionals, and philanthropic foundations, which I call the new child savers, strategically sowed doubt about the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders to ensure the success of this new discourse of immaturity. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance to explain how they strategically concealed this inconvenient knowledge to achieve the socially valued goal of “saving children” from harsh sentences, and to escape public controversies over the racial overtones of risk assessment tools. Second, using Mills’ s concept of white ignorance, I argue that progressive elites and scholars involved in juvenile justice reform have historically ignored the lived experiences of juveniles of color. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of brain immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a colorblind explanation of juvenile crime that ignores the role of race in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Summary

The legal treatment of juvenile offenders has been a subject of ongoing debate. While initially guided by rehabilitative ideals, the late 20th century saw a punitive shift emphasizing punishment and incarceration. However, a subsequent focus on rehabilitation emerged, fueled by Supreme Court decisions referencing neuroscientific evidence of adolescent brain immaturity. This "discourse of immaturity," while influential in reforming juvenile justice, has faced criticism for its omission of race as a significant factor in the disparate treatment of juvenile offenders within the criminal justice system. This article critiques this omission, arguing that the discourse of immaturity, while seemingly benevolent, inadvertently perpetuates existing racial inequalities.

Ignorance and the Absent Presence of Race

The discourse of immaturity, while seemingly objective, has been criticized for its failure to address racial disparities within the juvenile justice system. This omission, it is argued, is not accidental but a product of both passive and intentional processes of ignorance. Established criminological knowledge regarding "life-course persistent offenders"—a small group disproportionately responsible for violent crime—was strategically downplayed to bolster the more palatable narrative of universal adolescent immaturity. This strategic ignorance, aimed at achieving a socially valued goal (rehabilitation), highlights the complexities of benevolent ignorance in social justice movements. The article utilizes existing frameworks of agnotology and the "coloniality of knowledge" to analyze the implications of this omission.

Data and Methods

The research employed a mixed-methods approach, incorporating data from semi-structured interviews with key figures involved in the development and dissemination of neurolaw, legal materials from landmark Supreme Court cases, and a comparative discourse analysis of amicus briefs submitted to the Supreme Court. This method allowed for exploration of the interplay between scientific discourse, legal arguments, and the broader social context shaping the discourse of immaturity. The focus on amicus briefs, as hybrid legal-scientific documents, provides unique insight into the boundary work at the intersection of science and law.

The Punitive Turn and the Superpredator Narrative

The rise of a punitive approach to juvenile justice in the 1980s and 1990s was influenced by criminological research on "high-risk delinquents" and the concurrent public narrative of "superpredators." This narrative, often implicitly racialized, contributed to harsher sentencing laws and a heightened focus on punishment. The resulting political climate and public perception created a context for the subsequent emergence of the discourse of immaturity as a counter-narrative.

The New Child Savers and the Discourse of Immaturity

In response to the punitive turn, the MacArthur Foundation funded research aiming to shift the focus back to rehabilitation. This initiative, involving academics, legal professionals, and juvenile justice advocates, strategically emphasized the neuroscientific evidence of adolescent brain immaturity to support legal challenges to harsh sentencing. This "discourse of immaturity" proved remarkably effective in legal arenas.

The Benevolent Ignorance of Inconvenient Knowledge

To successfully promote the discourse of immaturity, researchers and advocates largely disregarded established criminological knowledge about "high-risk" offenders. This "benevolent ignorance," while furthering a progressive goal, raises questions about the ethical implications of selectively utilizing scientific evidence to support a particular narrative. The article explores the motivations behind this omission, highlighting the tension between well-intentioned reform and the perpetuation of systemic inequalities.

The Superpredator: Science, Racism, and Politics

The "superpredator" narrative of the 1990s, often implicitly associating this stereotype with young Black men, contributed to the punitive turn in juvenile justice. The association of risk assessment tools with racial bias, coupled with incidents like the “monkeys in a jungle” comparison, further fueled criticism of the punitive approach. The MacArthur Foundation, having previously supported risk-assessment research, strategically distanced itself from these controversies as the discourse of immaturity gained prominence.

The Dark Side of Benevolence

The discourse of immaturity, despite its seemingly benevolent aims, is criticized for its inherent "white ignorance." This critique centers on the historical construction of developmental norms primarily based on white, privileged children, and the subsequent application of these norms to a racially diverse population within the juvenile justice system. This "default whiteness" in neuroscientific research obscures racial disparities in the system and reinforces a color-blind approach to justice.

Conclusion

The discourse of immaturity, while achieving significant legal and political reform, ultimately perpetuates a color-blind understanding of juvenile crime. The article concludes by emphasizing the complex interplay between scientific knowledge, social structures, and the perpetuation of systemic inequalities. The contrast between the U.S. approach, heavily reliant on neuroscience, and European approaches that emphasize broader sociopolitical factors highlights the limitations of a purely neurobiological framing of juvenile justice reform.

Abstract

The criminal culpability of juvenile offenders remains a controversial and contested issue in the legal and public arenas in the United States. Since the mid-2000s, juvenile crime has been reframed by SCOTUS as a problem of brain immaturity. This article interrogates the omission of race from this new discourse of immaturity. First, I show that an alliance of learned societies, scholars, policy experts, legal professionals, and philanthropic foundations, which I call the new child savers, strategically sowed doubt about the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders to ensure the success of this new discourse of immaturity. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance to explain how they strategically concealed this inconvenient knowledge to achieve the socially valued goal of “saving children” from harsh sentences, and to escape public controversies over the racial overtones of risk assessment tools. Second, using Mills’ s concept of white ignorance, I argue that progressive elites and scholars involved in juvenile justice reform have historically ignored the lived experiences of juveniles of color. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of brain immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a colorblind explanation of juvenile crime that ignores the role of race in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Summary

The legal treatment of juvenile offenders has been a subject of ongoing debate. While the early 20th century saw the establishment of juvenile courts emphasizing rehabilitation, a shift towards punitive measures and incarceration gained momentum in the latter half of the century. This change was fueled by criminological research focusing on individual risk assessment. However, a subsequent reevaluation occurred in the mid-2000s, leading to Supreme Court decisions that overturned the death penalty and life without parole for juveniles, based on emerging neuroscientific evidence emphasizing the immaturity of the adolescent brain.

The Discourse of Immaturity and its Critiques

This "discourse of immaturity," highlighting the underdeveloped adolescent brain as a mitigating factor in criminal behavior, garnered significant support among juvenile justice advocates. However, this approach has faced criticism from various scholars. Social scientists have questioned the causal link between neurobiological development and risky behavior, while legal scholars have challenged the Supreme Court's reliance on neuroscientific evidence and its legal applicability. The article proposes a different critique, focusing on the discourse's omission of race as a crucial factor influencing juvenile justice outcomes.

Ignorance and the Absent Presence of Race

The article argues that the discourse of immaturity, while seemingly neutral, is shaped by a "benevolent ignorance" of race. This "benevolent ignorance" strategically avoids acknowledging the well-established racial disparities within the juvenile justice system, where race is a significant predictor of negative outcomes. The authors examine how this omission perpetuates racial stratification within the criminal justice system, analyzing the historical context and the intentions of those involved in shaping the discourse. The authors examine how this omission functions as a political device and explores different types of scientific ignorance.

Data and Methods

The analysis draws on multiple sources including in-depth interviews with academics, judges, government officials, and juvenile justice advocates; legal materials from Supreme Court cases; and amicus briefs submitted to the court. A comparative discourse analysis is used to identify inconsistencies between scientific claims and legal arguments within these materials.

The Punitive Turn and the Superpredator Narrative

The 1980s and 90s witnessed a "punitive turn" in juvenile justice, driven partly by the emergence of the "superpredator" narrative. This narrative emphasized a small percentage of "high-risk" juvenile offenders responsible for a disproportionate amount of violent crime. This focus, coupled with rising crime rates and media attention, contributed to harsher sentencing laws and a shift away from rehabilitation. This created an environment where reformers sought a new approach.

The New Child Savers and the Discourse of Immaturity

In response to the punitive turn, the MacArthur Foundation funded research to counter this trend. A network of scholars, legal professionals, and others aimed to create a new framework emphasizing adolescent brain immaturity. This "new child savers" movement strategically used neuroscientific findings to create a more palatable narrative for legal reform, ultimately influencing landmark Supreme Court decisions.

Benevolent Ignorance of Inconvenient Knowledge

To successfully promote the discourse of immaturity, the "new child savers" strategically downplayed or ignored existing criminological research on high-risk offenders. This "benevolent ignorance," while motivated by a desire for social justice, inadvertently obscured the issue of racial disparities within the juvenile justice system. The research focuses on the strategies employed to avoid controversial information.

The Superpredator: Science, Racism, and Politics

The "superpredator" narrative, while not explicitly racist, carried strong racial undertones. It intersected with broader anxieties about changing demographics and crime, fueling support for stricter laws and further marginalizing young people of color within the justice system. Risk assessment tools, while ostensibly neutral, were applied in ways that disproportionately affected minority youth. The authors analyze the interplay of science, racism, and politics within the narrative.

The Dark Side of Benevolence

The article analyzes the concept of “white ignorance” and how this has shaped the child savers’ understanding of juvenile justice reform. The discourse of immaturity is deemed racially ignorant for relying on research predominantly conducted on white youth, and for failing to adequately address racial disparities in the justice system. The implications of this color-blind approach are discussed.

Conclusion

The discourse of immaturity, while having led to positive legal reforms, ultimately perpetuates a color-blind view of juvenile justice. It overlooks the systemic racial inequalities that disproportionately affect young people of color within the criminal justice system. The article concludes by highlighting the complexities of using scientific evidence to achieve social justice and the importance of critically examining the assumptions underlying such approaches.

Abstract

The criminal culpability of juvenile offenders remains a controversial and contested issue in the legal and public arenas in the United States. Since the mid-2000s, juvenile crime has been reframed by SCOTUS as a problem of brain immaturity. This article interrogates the omission of race from this new discourse of immaturity. First, I show that an alliance of learned societies, scholars, policy experts, legal professionals, and philanthropic foundations, which I call the new child savers, strategically sowed doubt about the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders to ensure the success of this new discourse of immaturity. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance to explain how they strategically concealed this inconvenient knowledge to achieve the socially valued goal of “saving children” from harsh sentences, and to escape public controversies over the racial overtones of risk assessment tools. Second, using Mills’ s concept of white ignorance, I argue that progressive elites and scholars involved in juvenile justice reform have historically ignored the lived experiences of juveniles of color. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of brain immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a colorblind explanation of juvenile crime that ignores the role of race in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Summary

The legal treatment of juvenile offenders has been a subject of ongoing debate. Initially, juvenile courts offered distinct treatment from adult courts, focusing on rehabilitation. However, a shift towards punishment and incarceration occurred in the late 20th century, driven by a risk-based model emphasizing individual culpability. This changed in the mid-2000s when Supreme Court decisions, citing neuroscientific evidence of adolescent brain immaturity, declared the death penalty and life without parole unconstitutional for juveniles.

The Discourse of Immaturity

This "discourse of immaturity" argued that adolescents' risky behavior stems from brain immaturity, warranting leniency. This idea gained traction, influencing juvenile justice reform and even extending the argument to young adults. However, this approach has faced criticism from various fields, questioning the causal link between brain development and behavior, and SCOTUS's reliance on amicus briefs.

Ignorance and the Absent Presence of Race

This article argues that the discourse of immaturity overlooks the racial disparities deeply embedded within the U.S. juvenile justice system. It examines how the construction of this discourse, driven by prominent learned societies and the MacArthur Foundation, involved a strategic ignoring of existing knowledge about "life-course persistent offenders"—a small group responsible for a disproportionate amount of violent crime. This "benevolent ignorance" aimed to achieve social justice but inadvertently perpetuated existing racial inequalities.

Data and Methods

The analysis draws upon interviews with academics, judges, officials, and advocates, and examines Supreme Court cases and amicus briefs, applying comparative discourse analysis to identify discursive inconsistencies. The research highlights the role of amicus briefs in mobilizing science within legal arguments.

The Punitive Turn and the Superpredator Narrative

The 1980s and 90s saw a focus on "high-risk delinquents" and the emergence of the "superpredator" narrative, fueled by criminological research and media portrayals. This contributed to harsher sentencing laws. This punitive approach was challenged by progressive groups who felt the focus had shifted away from the core principles of juvenile justice.

The New Child Savers and the Discourse of Immaturity

The MacArthur Foundation's research network aimed to counter the punitive turn by providing scientific evidence emphasizing adolescent immaturity. This collaborative effort between academics, legal professionals, and learned societies successfully shaped Supreme Court decisions. However, this involved strategically downplaying the existence and significance of "high-risk" offenders.

Benevolent Ignorance of Inconvenient Knowledge

The researchers intentionally distanced themselves from criminological findings on "high-risk" offenders, focusing instead on the broader concept of adolescent immaturity. This "benevolent ignorance" was crucial to the success of the immaturity discourse in legal settings, but it masked inconvenient truths regarding racial disparities.

The Superpredator: Science, Racism, and Politics

The "superpredator" narrative of the 1990s, often associated with racial minorities, fueled harsher sentencing. Risk assessment tools, initially intended for rehabilitation, were also used for surveillance and control, particularly targeting inner-city youth. The controversy surrounding these practices highlighted the inherent risk of racial bias.

The Dark Side of Benevolence

The article explores how "white ignorance," rooted in historical biases, blinded the child savers to racial inequalities. The discourse of immaturity, while seemingly neutral, reproduced a color-blind vision of juvenile justice that failed to address the disproportionate impact on youth of color.

Conclusion

While the discourse of immaturity achieved significant reform, it also perpetuated a color-blind understanding of juvenile delinquency, neglecting the impact of racial inequalities. The article concludes by emphasizing the need to acknowledge the social context of scientific knowledge and the ethical dilemmas of benevolent ignorance in achieving social justice.

Abstract

The criminal culpability of juvenile offenders remains a controversial and contested issue in the legal and public arenas in the United States. Since the mid-2000s, juvenile crime has been reframed by SCOTUS as a problem of brain immaturity. This article interrogates the omission of race from this new discourse of immaturity. First, I show that an alliance of learned societies, scholars, policy experts, legal professionals, and philanthropic foundations, which I call the new child savers, strategically sowed doubt about the criminological evidence of “high-risk” offenders to ensure the success of this new discourse of immaturity. I introduce the concept of benevolent ignorance to explain how they strategically concealed this inconvenient knowledge to achieve the socially valued goal of “saving children” from harsh sentences, and to escape public controversies over the racial overtones of risk assessment tools. Second, using Mills’ s concept of white ignorance, I argue that progressive elites and scholars involved in juvenile justice reform have historically ignored the lived experiences of juveniles of color. Finally, I discuss how the discourse of brain immaturity perpetuates and reinforces a colorblind explanation of juvenile crime that ignores the role of race in young people’s encounters with the justice system.

Summary

For a long time, people have debated how the law should treat kids who break the law. It's a tough question because it's hard to know exactly why kids should be treated differently than adults. In the US, special courts for kids started in 1899. But later, things changed. Starting in the 1980s, the focus shifted from helping kids to punishing them more. This meant more kids went to jail.

Then, around 2005, things started to change again. The Supreme Court said that it's not fair to give kids the death penalty or life in prison without a chance of getting out. They used new scientific ideas about how kids' brains are still growing and aren't fully developed. This new way of thinking helped people who wanted to help kids, not just punish them. It also made people think that young adults, under 21, should also get better treatment.

But some scientists and lawyers disagreed. They said the science wasn't strong enough to say that all kids should be treated more gently. They also pointed out that the system has always treated kids of different races differently and this new idea didn't really fix that. It didn't take into account that many more kids of color end up in the justice system.

Ignorance and the Absent Presence of Race

Scientists have always worried about using biology to explain why people commit crimes. It can make people ignore things like poverty and racism that also play a big part. But the new ideas about kids' brains were different. Older ideas looked at specific problems in people’s brains to predict who would commit crimes. The new idea said that all kids are more likely to take risks because their brains are not fully grown. It didn't talk about how race affects this.

Scientists say that ignoring race in science is a problem. Sometimes, ideas about race are hidden, but they still affect how things work. For example, even if a test doesn't seem to be about race, it might still be used in ways that hurt people of color. This is important because it shows that scientists' ideas, even if they mean well, can still hurt certain groups. It's also important to know who is doing the research and how their ideas affect what they do.

Data and Methods

This research looked at interviews with many different people involved in the legal system and science, like judges, lawyers, and scientists. They talked about how science is used in legal cases involving children who have committed crimes. The researchers also studied important Supreme Court cases where judges ruled on how to punish kids who commit crimes. They also examined what scientists wrote in legal documents trying to influence those court decisions.

The Punitive Turn and the Superpredator Narrative

In the 1980s and 1990s, some scientists said a small group of kids were responsible for most serious crimes. These kids were sometimes called "superpredators." This idea, along with news stories that focused on violent crime by kids, led to tougher laws and more kids going to jail. Some people thought this was unfair and that it ignored reasons why some kids got in trouble.

The new Child Savers and the Discourse of Immaturity

A group funded by the MacArthur Foundation wanted to change how people viewed kids in trouble. They gathered information about how kids' brains develop and used it to argue that kids should be treated more gently. This worked, and helped change laws about the death penalty for juveniles. But to succeed, they mostly ignored the idea that some kids were simply more likely to commit crimes than others.

The Benevolent Ignorance of Inconvenient Knowledge

To make their argument, the scientists chose to not use some other scientific information that showed some kids are more likely to commit crimes than others. This was to avoid arguments about the reasons for this that sometimes had to do with racism. They wanted to focus on the idea that all kids need help, not punishment.

The Superpredator: Science, Racism and Politics

In the 1990s, many people worried about rising crime rates. Some scientists and politicians said that young black men were committing most crimes. This idea was used to support stricter laws, and this often unfairly targeted minority groups. Some research programs tried to find ways to identify kids likely to commit crimes, but this was criticized for being racist. The MacArthur Foundation, which helped fund these programs, later shifted its focus and did not continue with this type of research.

The Dark Side of Benevolence

The idea that kids' brains are still developing was used to help kids, but it didn't fix the problem of racism in the justice system. The scientists who supported the new way of thinking didn't always fully understand how racism has affected the justice system. This was partly because the scientific research about kids’ brains didn't include enough people of color.

Conclusion

Using science to change how kids are treated in the legal system has had good and bad results. It did help make the system fairer for some kids, but it also ignored how race has a big impact on how kids are treated. The system needs to consider all factors, not just kids’ brain development. Other countries handle these issues differently, without focusing so much on science.

Footnotes and Citation

Cite

Wannyn, W. (2024). “Kids are Kids”: Benevolent Ignorance and the Omission of Race in Developmental Justice Reform. Science, Technology, & Human Values, 01622439241264028. https://doi.org/10.1177/01622439241264028

    Highlights